serve the use of all, in the spirit of the proverb which says ‘Friends’ goods are goods in
common’. (Politics, 1263a, in Barker, 1952. p. 49)
in his justification of slavery, Aristotle also developed the argument that knowledge is a
basis for asserting ownership, and in the case of slavery, of course, ownership means direct
interpersonal dominance. Aristotle argued that the essence of property is its instrumentality.
It serves as a subordinate part or extension of the owner. Property has no life or being other
than that of belonging. It lacks its own telic self-direction, which in man is based on knowledge
and reason. Just as the soul controls and owns the body because the superior reason of the
soul can direct the care and use of the body in a beneficial and productive manner, so too does
the superior knowledge of the master justify his control and ownership of the slave:
A man is thus by nature a slave if he is capable of becoming (and this is the reason why
he also actually becomes) the property of another, and if he participates in reason to the
extent of apprehending it in another, though destitute of it himself. Herein he differs from
animals, which do not apprehend reason, but simply obey their instincts. But the use which
is made of the slave diverges but little from the use made of tame animals; both he and they
supply their owner with bodily help in meeting his daily requirements. (Politics, 1254b, in
Barker, 1952, p. 13)
However, Aristotle does make it clear that control and enslavement of others by mere physical
power is unjust.
Aristotle also leaves suggestions that property serves a communicative, symbolic
function. For example, in his discussion of the proper use of wealth, he mentions that the
display of wealth should not be for self-regard but for public benefit:
For the magnificent man spends not on himself but on public objects, and gifts bear some
resemblance to votive offerings. A magnificent man will also furnish his house suitably to
his wealth for even a house is a sort of public ornament. (Ethics, IV. 2, in Ross, 1983, p. 84)
In another example, Aristotle explains how wealth serves as a sign from which superior moral
gualities are inferred:
...culture and breeding, the attributes of aristocracy, are more associated with the wealthier
classes who form the basis of oligarchy. We may also note as explaining this common
usage of the term ‘aristocracy’ that the wealthy are generally supposed to possess already
the advantages for want of which wrongdoers fall into crime; and this Is the reason why they
are called ‘gentlemen’ or ‘notables’. Now as aristocracy aims at giving preeminence to the
best, men are led in this way to extend the term and to describe oligarchies too as states
governed by gentlemen. (Politics, IV 1293b, in Barker, 1952, p. 175)
Finally, Aristotle’s discussion of property draws upon cross-cultural and cross-species
comparisons. In his rebuttal to Plato, Aristotle (Barker, 1952) cites examples of property
practices in Arcadia, Athens, Crete, Carthage, Libya, Lorcia, Miletus, Sparta, Thebes, Thessaly
and Thrace. This was undoubtedly a part of Aristotle's larger survey of 158 social regimes
(Jaffa. 1963). Historically, Aristotle’s work was probably the first cross-cultural survey on a