A possession ought to belong to the possessor, not the possessor to the possession.
Whosoever, therefore, does not use his patrimony as a possession, who does not know how
to give and distribute to the poor, he is the servant of his wealth, not its master; because
like the servant he watches over the wealth of another, and not like a master does he use
it of his own. Hence, in disposition of this kind we say that the man belongs to his riches,
not the riches to the man. (St. Ambrose, De Nabuthe, 3, PL 14: 738, in Avila, 1983, p. 67)
St. Augustine similarly preached against attachment to property and the social discord such
attachment produced:
There are some things which are to be enjoyed, other which are to be used, others which
are enjoyed and used...To enjoy anything means to cling to it with affection for its own
sake. To use a thing is to employ what we have received for our use to obtain what we want,
provided that it is right for us to want it. An unlawfully applied use ought rather to be
termed an abuse....If we wish to return to our native country where we can be happy, we
must use this world and not enjoy it. (St. Augustine, De Doctrina Christiana, 1, 3-4, PL 34:
20-21, in Avila, 1983, p. 109)
Whence the discords among brethren?...Whence one womb, and not one soul? -if not for
the fact that as long as their soul Is crooked, those who possessed a share with their
brother or sister consider that share, and strive to enrich and increase it and wish to
consolidate everything in their possession. (St. Augustine, Sermo CCCLIX, 2, PL 39: 1591,
Avila, 1983, p. 117)
Renaissance & Reformation
However, by the late Middle Ages, Scholastics such as Alexander of Hales and Albertus
Magnus were arguing that although communal property was natural in a state of innocence,
private property was natural in the contemporary state of sin (Schlatter, 1951). This change, and
the rediscovery of Aristotle’s Politics, led to new attempts to develop natural explanations of
property. Aquinas was pivotal to this change. On the one hand, he continued the argument that
communal property was the ideal condition and that all men had a natural right to temporal
goods (Fredrickson, 1954; Maritain, 1933; Schlatter, 1951). He also held to the old claim that
knowledge of proper use is the ultimate justification for ownership:
...a thing is naturally commensurate with another person, not according as it is considered
absolutely, but according to something resultant from it, for instance the possession of
property. For if a particular piece of land be considered absolutely, it contains no reason
why it should belong to one man more than another, but if it be considered in respect of its
adaptability to cultivation, and the unmolested use of the land, it has a certain
commensuration to be the property of one and not of another man, as the philosopher
shows, Politics, Il. (Aquinas, Basic writings of St. Thomas, I-ll, Q. 94, in Schiatter, 1951, p. 49)
Aquinas also retained the Christian belief that all property is held in stewardship.
On the other hand, Aquinas revived the Aristotelian claim that owning property is a natural,
innate, legitimate pleasure (Maritain, 1933). The argument, presented in Fredrickson’s (1954)
scholastic thesis on The Psychology of Ownership, is this: all things belong to God, and man’s