literature of the ownership of dreams, names, songs, and other immaterial property. In their
discussions of owning, several psychologists have enumerated cognitive objects as possible
possessions:
..this extends from material objects to lay hold, in the same spirit, of the attentions and
affections of other people, of all sorts of plans and ambitions, including the noblest special
purposes the mind can entertain, and indeed of any conceivable idea which may come to
seem a part of one’s life and in need of assertion against someone else. (Cooley, 1902, pp.
148)
Possessions, friends, one’s own children, other children, cultural interests, abstract ideas,
politics, hobbies, recreation, and most conspicuously of all, one’s work, all lead to the
incorporation of interests once remote from the self into selfhood proper. (Allport, 1937,
p. 217)
..although as a rule we confine ourselves above all to material possessions, it is evident
that both ideas and objects can be equally well acquired and conserved, can be worked
upon, transferred and abandoned. (Litwinski, 1947, p. 241)
To this list may be added James (1890), Sartre (1943/1956), Marcel (1949), Altman (1970), Fromm
(1976) and Nuttin (1987). However, Prelinger’s (1959) data show ideas not to be possessed as
a part of the Self. Henry James (1852) and Dewey (1898/1976) have argued that moral qualities
can be treated as possessions, though they believe it a moral mistake to do so.
Abelson (1986) has recently reviewed the social psychological literature on beliefs.
Independent of the psychological discussions of property and possession, he has made the
argument that beliefs are like possessions. He concluded that the possession of a belief may
be induced by various methods of cognitively elaborating the belief or of establishing social
recognition of its possession. This is not unlike McClelland’s (1965) description of the
acquisition of a motive, though that discussion was couched more in behavioral and personality
terminology than in cognitive terminology. Prentice (1987) is the first to provide empirical
evidence that there is a psychological correspondence between the possession of material
objects and such mental objects as attitudes and values.
It is important to realize in these discussions of ideas and beliefs as possessions that they
may be either private and exclusive or common and shared. Unexpressed ideas certainly are
private and expressed ideas are public but may be treated as private by social conventions or
jaw. But there is not the inherent basis for exclusive possession of ideas and beliefs as there
is with material possessions. Owning as knowing thus does not so much involve dominance
and control through exclusion, but, if at all, through the mastery and possession of people
discussed by Nietzsche, Sartre and Eigen.